Ockham, William (William of Occam) (ca. 1288–1347). Encyclopedia of Medieval Literature

One of the most significant theologians and
philosophers of late medieval Europe, William of
Ockham is generally considered to be the first
“nominalist” thinker, so called because his position on universals held that they were only names,
or terms, and unlike specific individuals, did not
exist in reality. Ockham is also famous for his
writings on logic, wherein he formulated the famous “Ockham’s razor”—the dictum that the
simplest explanation is likely the truth. Though
his philosophical contributions are significant, it
should be remembered that Ockham thought of
himself as a theologian first, and specifically as a
Franciscan theologian, since he belonged to that
order. He spent much of the latter part of his life
in conflict with the pope over ideas of ecclesiastical poverty, a doctrine of some interest to followers of St. F
RANCIS.
Born around 1288, most likely in the village of
Ockham in Surrey, William joined the Franciscan
order as a teenager. He was ordained a subdeacon
in 1306, and in about 1309 went to study at Oxford. He began giving lectures on P
ETER LOMBARD’s
Sentences in 1317, and quickly achieved an international reputation in the field of logic, developing
the formula that became his “razor”: “plurality
should not be assumed without necessity” (Adams
1987, I, 156). His opinions were controversial,
however, and he was never awarded a chair at Oxford. After 1321, he seems to have left Oxford to
teach in London. Probably all of his nonpolitical
writings were written before 1324, when he was
summoned to Avignon to answer charges of
heresy, chiefly in his famous commentary on the
Sentences. In 1326, a papal commission censured
51 of Ockham’s propositions, though none was
ever officially condemned by the pope.
The papacy had been located at Avignon since
the beginning of the century, and Ockham found it
a den of corruption. While waiting for his own case
to be decided, he met the general of the Franciscan Order, Michael of Cesena, who was involved in
a controversy with Pope John XXII over belief in
the poverty of Jesus and his disciples, and its implication for the church—a doctrine the pope was
planning to condemn. Ockham joined Cesena in
defending the doctrine of ecclesiastical poverty. In
1328, he and Cesena fled from Avignon and joined
the court of the Holy Roman Emperor Louis of
Bavaria in Munich. From here the excommunicated Ockham wrote a number of attacks on the
pope, accusing him of seven separate heresies and
a number of other errors, including claiming more
power than God ever intended for a single person.
For the last two decades of his life, Ockham remained under the emperor’s protection and continued to publish political treatises against the
power of John XXII and subsequent popes. He

died in Munich on April 10, 1347, and was buried
at the Franciscan church there. Some believe that
he died of the B
LACK DEATH, though most scholars
now find that unlikely.
Ockham’s most important works are his commentary on the
Sentences, called the Ordinatio
(1321–23), his chief work on logic, called the
Summa logicae (ca. 1323), and the Quodlibeta septum (ca. 1323). His chief political works, written
mainly from Munich, include the
Opus nonaginta
dierum
and the Dialogus. It is important to remember that in all of his writings, Ockham was working
within the Franciscan tradition. This is obvious in
his political writings, stemming from the controversy over ecclesiastical poverty. But his philosophical and theological tracts are equally Franciscan in
their concerns, often building upon or reacting to
his great Franciscan predecessor D
UNS SCOTUS.
In general Ockham bases his theology and philosophy on two basic principles: first, that God’s
power is absolute, and cannot be limited by anything but his own will. This is God’s
potentia absoluta, his power considered in and of itself. God’s
power in creation—his creation of natural laws,
for instance—is God’s
potentia ordinata, his power
as exercised in the world. But Ockham insists that
all creation is contingent on God, and that God is
not limited by the laws of his creation except as far
as he himself wills it. The second chief principle is
that nothing actually exists except individuals and
their qualities, and all human experience consists
of our knowledge of these individuals—the chief
feature of nominalism. It is important to note that
the
via moderna, the chief school of Western philosophy for the two centuries following Ockham, is
based essentially on these principles. Further, in his
political writings, Ockham’s insistence on the separation of church and state anticipates modern political philosophy. In short, his influence on late
medieval thinkers, writers as well as theologians,
was profound, and a number of scholars have recently examined the influence of nominalism on
texts like Chaucer’s
CLERKS TALE and other writings. Ockham also influenced reforming theologians who followed him, particularly those who
advocated general councils to govern the church in
the early 15th century.
Bibliography
Adams, Marilyn McCord. William Ockham. 2 vols.
Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1987.
Boehner, Philotheus, ed. and trans.
William of Ockham: Philosophical Writings: A Selection. Edinburgh: Nelson and Sons, 1962.
Courtenay, William J.
Schools and Scholars in Fourteenth-Century England. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1987.
Peck, Russell A. “Chaucer and the Nominalist Questions,”
Speculum 53 (1978): 745–760.
Ruud, Jay. “Chaucer and Nominalism:
The Envoy to
Bukton,
Mediaevalia 10 (1984): 199–212.
Spade, Paul Vincent.
The Cambridge Companion to
Ockham.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999.
Utz, Richard J.
Literary Nominalism and the Theory of
Rereading Late Medieval Texts: A New Research
Paradigm.
Medieval Studies, 5. Lewiston, N.Y.:
Edwin Mellen Press, 1995.

Leave a Reply 0

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *