X

The Cambridge Companion to Theodore Dreiser (Cambridge Companions to Literature)

here is that there exists no economy, no need to give something in return for

something you take, no law or rule that governs gift-giving. In this sense of

the word, the phrase “economy of the gift” is merely an excuse for escaping

from any and all economy.9

116

Dreiser and upward mobility

One such economy is that of gender. Seeing loyalty as a free gift is conve-

nient for men, who can unconsciously expect that they will receive loyalties

and other services from their womenfolk for which no recompense or re-

muneration of any kind will be required. It encourages men to think of

themselves as children to whom everything is owed. The assumed or ideal

perspective here would seem to be that of the male (as) child. For the male

child, love is not only speculation, entailing no reciprocal obligations, but –

to the extent that he functions within a gender system or economy – it is an

inevitably successful speculation, an investment with a high and guaranteed return. This point helps explain the direction in which loyalty or emotional

capital will flow between Frank and his wife and mistress.10

But from the perspective of Frank’s public guilt or lack of it, the most

important economic reality that is evaded by speaking of an “economy of

the gift” is that which links finance via gifts – or bribes – to the power of

the state. No, you cannot steal that which is freely given. But who gives

Frank Cowperwood the funds he is accused of stealing? The only plausible

way to use the word gift in this context is if one identifies the giver as city treasurer Stener, a corrupt pawn of the Republican political machine then

ruling Philadelphia. Stener did not have the right to profit from, or to allow

Cowperwood to profit from, money that belonged to the people of the city of

Philadelphia. Like so many other financiers, Cowperwood makes his fortune

not on the open market but on the contrary by using political connections

to obtain illegal access to public funds and thus manipulating the market.

Butler’s upward mobility story, which makes possible Frank’s own, differs

from it only in minor details. Butler is “a poor young Irishman” who col-

lects garbage for free and feeds it to his pigs and cattle until “a local political character, a councilman friend of his,” has an idea. “Butler could be made

official garbage-collector. The council could vote an annual appropriation

for this service. Butler could employ more wagons than he did now – dozens

of them, scores. Not only that, but no other garbage-collector would be al-

lowed. There were others, but the official contract awarded to him would

also, officially, be the end of the life of any and every disturbing rival” (11).

Like Butler, Cowperwood derives his profits from the fact that the market

is not open but on the contrary closed down with help from official friends, made into a monopoly by the direct exercise of state power. Understandably

enough, Michaels underplays this state-oriented side of “finance capitalism,”

for it gives the supposedly victimless crime a source and a victim: the inhab-

itants of the city of Philadelphia.

But can the city of Philadelphia be properly described as a victim? In

response to the argument above, one might well object that the city does

not manifest collective consciousness of its interests or otherwise assert its

117

b ru c e ro b b i n s

existence and rights, thus proving it is an entity capable of sustaining injury.

The ethical standards by which such an act might be judged are appropriate

to it only if it is a real entity. But a city is not real in the way a person

is real. Even now, who would suggest that one should be loyal or even

can be loyal to a city in the way one is expected to be loyal to a person?

And in historical perspective, the incongruity is even more stark. It might

be proposed, that is, that people had not yet come to see the abuse of the

municipality for private advantage as illegitimate. “There was a political

ring in Philadelphia in which the mayor, certain members of the council, the

treasurer, the chief of police, the commissioner of public works, and others

shared. It was a case generally of ‘you scratch my back, I’ll scratch yours.’

Cowperwood thought it rather shabby work at first, but many men were

rapidly getting rich and no one seemed to care. The newspapers were always

talking about civic patriotism and pride but never a word about these things”

(10). “No one seemed to care”: in the period Dreiser was describing, in other

words, there existed little if any organized public opinion that defined such

behavior as a crime, few if any representatives of the city of Philadelphia

who were ready to contest the legitimacy of what Butler, Cowperwood,

Mollenhauer, and their cronies were doing. The newspapers are silent. The

Municipal Reform Association is described as ineffectual. For all intents and

purposes, the relevant ethics was not yet in place. And not all that much has

changed. Outcry against the immense corporate scandals of our own time,

such as Enron and WorldCom, again involving direct collaboration between

financiers and their friends in the government, again involving a failure to

rescue the victims from statistical anonymity and put faces on them, has

again been pitifully weak, thus suggesting that such an ethics is still very

flimsily implanted in the public sphere, that the public is still very much

at risk of under-representation and under-protection. All the more reason,

then, to understand Dreiser’s lack of outrage against Cowperwood, and the

uninhibited excitement Dreiser seems to permit himself at the possibility of

making fortunes in an ethical area still thought of as gray.

All of this is true enough, and yet the history is in fact a bit more com-

plicated. In the period in which Dreiser was writing, elements of this new

ethical sensibility were already starting to emerge, even if they had not yet

quite cohered. Large institutional entities suddenly demanded to be treated

as real persons. They demanded loyalty, and in doing so they also redefined

loyalty. The claims made for these newly emergent entities – I’m speaking

most obviously of corporations – were necessarily accompanied by stren-

uous ethical re-arrangements. The very concept of a corporation required

a re-definition of what was and was not criminal or blameworthy. Limited

liability had of course been resisted initially on the grounds that it subverted 118

Dreiser and upward mobility

proper personal responsibility for one’s debts, that is, for one’s actions. With the rise of the corporation, the conventional system of exchange between an

action (for example, a piece of work accomplished or a theft) and its reward

or punishment was disturbed, and the meaning of loyalty along with it. It is

this disturbance that Michaels’ argument both reflects and misinterprets. For

the subverting of a previously transparent relation between an action and

its reward or punishment does not happen solely at the behest of corporate

capitalism. Rising along with the corporation are similarly large, abstract,

impersonal entities like the city government of Philadelphia.11 And, some-

what more slowly, at the federal, state, and municipal levels, what will come

to be called the “welfare state.”

Often these official entities seem to come after and in response to capital-

ism. But as we saw above, they may also serve as hidden source of the funds

that will then be displayed as the supposed fruit of a capitalist’s hard work

and financial wizardry. In terms of timing, the period of what Michaels calls

“finance capitalism” more or less coincides with the period of the expan-

sion of government and the rise of the welfare state. And in order to rise,

the welfare state too needed to shift decisively the meaning of individual

responsibility. To put this as pithily as possible: once upon a time, if you

were homeless, it was because you refused to work. Poverty was equated

with moral failure. There could be no move in the direction of what we now

call welfare – state responsibility to care for those most in need – until the

equation of poverty with immorality had been broken, until responsibility

for poverty had come to be seen as (at least in part) systemic and shared

rather than exclusively individual, until the general ethical sensibility had

swerved in the direction of “no fault.”

The modifications thus entailed in the notion of the accountable self are

a central theme of Howard Horwitz’s By the Law of Nature: Form and

Value in Nineteenth-Century America, which finds illustrations in Dreiser’s financier. Though Cowperwood is “frequently called self-reliant and self-sufficient,” Horwitz shows, his upward mobility story is not in fact an ex-

ample of “Emersonian self-reliance.”12 On the contrary, it is achieved by

“an effacement of agency” (197). Cowperwood exercises power “by taking

himself off the market” (198). Though the example Horwitz is mainly inter-

Page: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71

Categories: Dreiser, Theodore
curiosity: